Empower your legal journey with our comprehensive legal resocurces

Views of Salmond in Legal Realism as expounded by Holmes


Introduction:

One version of legal realism was the one propounded by Samlond, who pointed out that all law, is not made by the legislature. In fact he argued that in England much of it was made by law courts. Nevertheless, all laws, however made, are recognized and administered by the courts. Therefore, if a rule is not recognized by a Court, it is not a rule of law. Thus, according to Salmond, it is the courts and not the legislature that we must turn to if we wish to ascertain the true nature of law. Accordingly, he defined law as the body of principles recognized and applied by the State in the administration of justice, as the rules recognized and acted upon by the Courts.

However, there has been another version of legal realism, particularly in the United States of America. According to this theory propounded by American jurists, law is in reality judge-made. The origin of this theory is traced to Justice Holmes, and the theory has a substantial following in the United States.

Holmes highlights the situation not of the judge or the lawyer, but of what he calls ‘the bad man’, i.e. the man who is anxious to secure his own selfish interests. Such a man is not interested in knowing what the statutes or the text books say, but what the Courts are likely to do in fact. This theory makes a distinction between law in books and law in action.

According to this theory, what the courts will actually do cannot necessarily be deduced from the rules of law in text books or even from the words of the statutes themselves, since it is for the Courts to say what the words mean. As Gray observed, “The Courts put life into the dead words of the statute.” This approach is a reaction to the traditional approach that judges do not really create the law, but only declare what the law already is.

This school fortifies sociological jurisprudence, and recognizes law as the result of social influence and conditions and regards it as based on judicial decisions. In the words of Holmes,



“The life of the law has not been logic; it has been experience.” Or as Paton pointed out, “Law is what the Courts do; it is not merely what the Courts say. The emphasis is on action.”

However, the American realists point out that when Courts must choose between alternatives, much will depend on the subjective element of a judge. The judicial process, they argue, is not like that of a slot machine. Much will depend on the temperament, upbringing, social background, realities, learning etc of the judge. Therefore, they contend that law is nothing more than the prediction of what the Courts will decide.

It is also argued that the language of several statutes is uncertain and the Courts are therefore called upon to decide what a particular word or phrase means. Thus, for instance, the English Road Traffic Act makes it an offence to drive a vehicle in a manner dangerous to the public. An interesting question brought before the Court was whether a person who steers a broken down vehicle on tow can be said to be driving it.

Since the Parliament and not defined the word ‘driving’, the word would have to be understood in the ordinary sense. However, the ordinary usage of the word is not wide enough to cope up with such a marginal situation, as it does not draw a very clear or distinct line between what is driving and what is not driving. Faced with this question for the first time in 1946, the Court had to draw such an arbitrary line and further define the term ‘driving’ in Wallace v. Major.

A note can also be made of Scandinavian Realism, the founder whereof was Axel Hagerstrom. Whilst the American realists preferred to revolve around what the Courts did and what the judges said, the Scandinavian School sought to develop a formal philosophy of law, showing how law is not an inextricable part of society as a whole. The Scandinavian Realist does not look at law as a divine command. According to them, law creates morality and not the other way around.

Criticism

The view that a statement of law is nothing more than a prediction of what the Courts will decide is subject to certain criticism.



Legal situations are not predictions

It should be noted that a statement of law is seldom treated as a prediction, which a counsel submits before a Court. He is not forecasting what the judge will decide, but he is asking what the judge should decide. Further, a judicial decision is not a prediction of what the higher Courts would do, but it is a judgment as to what the law now is. Similarly, a legislature is not predicting what will be done, but it lays down what shall be done.

The theory represents a fraction of the situation

Though the realist view may be true to some extent in those situations when a new principle of law is evolved, yet it should be noted that most of our law is settled and stabilized. It should also be noted that several points of law never reach the Court, for the simple reason that the principle of law is so clear that the parties adhere to it.

Thus, it is argued that the creative days of the judge is now a thing of the past. It is argued that today the law is so complete that the task of the judges is the more or less automatic task of applying settled laws to the cases before them.

However, this criticism is not without an answer. Legal rules are still not as certain as was once imagined and the element of choice still faces a Court of law. To quote one example, in England the unlawful and intentional killing of a human being is the common law crime of murder. But what would be the position if X intentionally inflicts a mortal wound on Y, and then, mistakenly thinking him to de dead, throws the body into a lake, with the result that Y dies, not from the wound but from drowning? Would this amount to murder? Until 1954, the English law had no answer to this question, when these facts were before the Court in Thabo Meli v. R, in which case the Court had to further develop the English law of murder.

The theory of uncertainty of language is not always correct

It may be noted that in some border-line cases, the language may be uncertain, as in the example of the word ‘driving’ given earlier. But to generalize that all language is uncertain is to exaggerate the situation without foundation. In marginal cases, the meaning of the word may be uncertain, but this proves that the meaning of the word is certain in other cases. Therefore, the realistic approach of law based on the uncertainty of language is a generalization of an exceptional situation.

Conclusion: 

The origin of the theory of Legal Realism can be traced to Justice Holmes. The theory propounds that it is the courts and not the legislature that we must turn to if we wish to ascertain the true nature of law. The theory works on the belief that “the Courts put life into the dead words of the statute.” However, there has been some criticism of this theory.

jurisprudence